text
stringlengths 0
74
|
---|
description, so that it might seem as if no difficulty would arise; |
but as soon as we try to be more precise our troubles begin. Although |
I believe that the table is 'really' of the same colour all over, the |
parts that reflect the light look much brighter than the other parts, |
and some parts look white because of reflected light. I know that, if |
I move, the parts that reflect the light will be different, so that the |
apparent distribution of colours on the table will change. It follows |
that if several people are looking at the table at the same moment, no |
two of them will see exactly the same distribution of colours, because |
no two can see it from exactly the same point of view, and any change in |
the point of view makes some change in the way the light is reflected. |
For most practical purposes these differences are unimportant, but to |
the painter they are all-important: the painter has to unlearn the habit |
of thinking that things seem to have the colour which common sense says |
they 'really' have, and to learn the habit of seeing things as they |
appear. Here we have already the beginning of one of the distinctions |
that cause most trouble in philosophy--the distinction between |
'appearance' and 'reality', between what things seem to be and what they |
are. The painter wants to know what things seem to be, the practical man |
and the philosopher want to know what they are; but the philosopher's |
wish to know this is stronger than the practical man's, and is more |
troubled by knowledge as to the difficulties of answering the question. |
To return to the table. It is evident from what we have found, that |
there is no colour which pre-eminently appears to be _the_ colour of the |
table, or even of any one particular part of the table--it appears to |
be of different colours from different points of view, and there is |
no reason for regarding some of these as more really its colour than |
others. And we know that even from a given point of view the colour will |
seem different by artificial light, or to a colour-blind man, or to a |
man wearing blue spectacles, while in the dark there will be no colour |
at all, though to touch and hearing the table will be unchanged. This |
colour is not something which is inherent in the table, but something |
depending upon the table and the spectator and the way the light falls |
on the table. When, in ordinary life, we speak of _the_ colour of the |
table, we only mean the sort of colour which it will seem to have to a |
normal spectator from an ordinary point of view under usual conditions |
of light. But the other colours which appear under other conditions |
have just as good a right to be considered real; and therefore, to avoid |
favouritism, we are compelled to deny that, in itself, the table has any |
one particular colour. |
The same thing applies to the texture. With the naked eye one can see |
the grain, but otherwise the table looks smooth and even. If we looked |
at it through a microscope, we should see roughnesses and hills and |
valleys, and all sorts of differences that are imperceptible to the |
naked eye. Which of these is the 'real' table? We are naturally tempted |
to say that what we see through the microscope is more real, but that in |
turn would be changed by a still more powerful microscope. If, then, we |
cannot trust what we see with the naked eye, why should we trust what we |
see through a microscope? Thus, again, the confidence in our senses with |
which we began deserts us. |
The shape of the table is no better. We are all in the habit of judging |
as to the 'real' shapes of things, and we do this so unreflectingly that |
we come to think we actually see the real shapes. But, in fact, as we |
all have to learn if we try to draw, a given thing looks different |
in shape from every different point of view. If our table is 'really' |
rectangular, it will look, from almost all points of view, as if it had |
two acute angles and two obtuse angles. If opposite sides are parallel, |
they will look as if they converged to a point away from the spectator; |
if they are of equal length, they will look as if the nearer side were |
longer. All these things are not commonly noticed in looking at a table, |
because experience has taught us to construct the 'real' shape from the |
apparent shape, and the 'real' shape is what interests us as practical |
men. But the 'real' shape is not what we see; it is something inferred |
from what we see. And what we see is constantly changing in shape as we |
move about the room; so that here again the senses seem not to give us |
the truth about the table itself, but only about the appearance of the |
table. |
Similar difficulties arise when we consider the sense of touch. It is |
true that the table always gives us a sensation of hardness, and we feel |
that it resists pressure. But the sensation we obtain depends upon how |
hard we press the table and also upon what part of the body we press |
with; thus the various sensations due to various pressures or various |
parts of the body cannot be supposed to reveal _directly_ any definite |
property of the table, but at most to be _signs_ of some property which |
perhaps _causes_ all the sensations, but is not actually apparent in any |
of them. And the same applies still more obviously to the sounds which |
can be elicited by rapping the table. |
Thus it becomes evident that the real table, if there is one, is not the |
same as what we immediately experience by sight or touch or hearing. The |
real table, if there is one, is not _immediately_ known to us at all, |
but must be an inference from what is immediately known. Hence, two very |
difficult questions at once arise; namely, (1) Is there a real table at |
all? (2) If so, what sort of object can it be? |
It will help us in considering these questions to have a few simple |
terms of which the meaning is definite and clear. Let us give the name |
of 'sense-data' to the things that are immediately known in sensation: |
such things as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and |
so on. We shall give the name 'sensation' to the experience of being |
immediately aware of these things. Thus, whenever we see a colour, |
we have a sensation _of_ the colour, but the colour itself is a |
sense-datum, not a sensation. The colour is that _of_ which we are |
immediately aware, and the awareness itself is the sensation. It is |
plain that if we are to know anything about the table, it must be |
Subsets and Splits